back toJacket2

Jacket 20 — December 2002   |   # 20  Contents   |   Homepage   |  Catalog   |



Hugh Sykes Davies

Sympathies With Surrealism

Back to Hugh Sykes Davies Contents list

This piece was first published in
New Verse, OS No. 20 (April–May 1936), pages 15–21.

It is 2,500 words or about six printed pages long.


There is going to be a surrealist exhibition in London in June. Of course it will be necessary to continue explaining what surrealism is; and of course this explanation will be given by the official leaders of the movement in Paris or by their accredited agents. This is very right. The leaders of the official movement have worked for many years with great industry, ability, and success; they are the only proper judges of what is surrealism, and who is surrealist.
      But apart from the official body and the official definitions, there are certain ‘sympathisers’ in England and elsewhere, whose position increasingly needs clarification, if it is possible to clarify it: — one might as well try.

Diver 2
I. There appear to be two ways of becoming a sympathiser, distinct in theory, and generally distinct in practice. First there is the way of simple souls, of practising artists who see or read official surrealist work, and respond to it strongly. Their own products are affected, and show ‘surrealist influence’: — in painting or in sculpture certain fairly specific shapes are employed, in poetry recognisable tricks of imagery and structure: — some young poets have attempted to transfer into English words the material of surrealist visual art. This influence can, of course, be less or more obvious, less or more successful, and it can be accompanied by a certain degree of theorising about the special nature of this kind of art. But since this theorising begins not from any stated theoretical problem: — since, further, this type of person is generally without great capacity or training for theoretical work: — and since the stimulus to theorising is not objectively observed phenomena, but a subjective experience, recorded by introspection: — in these conditions, the theory is of a poor quality. It consists in most cases of personal and verbal variations of traditional conceptions of ‘imagination,’ ‘inspiration,’ ‘direct intuition,’ and so on: — a sort of alluvial deposit from the main streams of European thought and religion of the last six centuries. The H.C.F of these semi-intellectual constructions is the view that a work of art is produced, wholly or in part, by the operation of some segment of the human personality which is not under the control of the will, and is not open to inspection or supervision by the intellect, either introspectively or in any other way. Of course this segment may be called ‘the unconscious.’ But unless the use of this word is accompanied by a fair understanding of the extended problems which lead up to, and which derive from, the hypothesis of the unconscious, its use must be dismissed as nothing more than a deceptive modernisation of vocabulary, concealing ancient ideas: — in all probability this ‘unconscious’ could not be distinguished from, for example, late Romantic ‘imagination,’ and it would be very much less confusing if it were still called imagination: — then we should at least know at once, without unnecessary expenditure of critical energy, that the whole construction could be dismissed out of hand.
      But this theoretical weakness need not prevent such people from producing good work: — even work is which hardly distinguishable from official surrealism, and which might be admitted officially as surrealist: — as the officials may decide. However, it is quite clear that, whatever the merits of their work, artists of this kind remain simple souls of the traditional type, working by ‘instinct,’ with a ramshackle codification of vague introspective data which may be of use to themselves, as scaffolding, and which is nothing but a nuisance to anyone else. And it must be admitted that if they are surrealists, in the full sense of the word, then surrealism is nothing new, and may be regarded as a development of late Romanticism.

Diver 3
II. The second way of becoming a sympathiser is not that of the simple souls.
      It is perfectly possible, in these days of universal education, for a creative artist to find himself confronted by certain theoretical problems at a very early stage in his development. He may well find that he has to solve some such problems, and arrive at some intellectual formulation, before he can create anything: — in direct contrast to the simple souls, who first create something, and then make a formula about it. For example, he may well ask himself such questions as these: ‘This activity will bring in little money, if any ; it will contribute nothing to the solution of my most direct problems; why, then, does the impulse to this activity persist?’ ‘Granting that in me this impulse exists, why does it apparently confine itself to so few people ; are we who suffer from it abnormal? If so, what has caused our abnormality? How can it best be overcome, by yielding to the impulse, or by resisting it? If by yielding, what kind of creative activity will give it the most complete and economical satisfaction?’’ All these questions might very reasonably occur, in one form or another, to any educated person, and the kind of answer given to them would influence very deeply the kind of creative work which might be produced.
      Now anyone occupied with such questions at any time and in almost any place during the last two decades has been compelled consider, at least, the claims of psychoanalysis to furnish a general theoretical background for the solution of his problems. those who have considered psychoanalysis most fully have generally found it more apt than any other system for their purpose. This has been the case with the official surrealists, and it has been the case with a number of independent artists.*

* I have omitted from the main line of my argument any consideration of the other main theoretical basis of surrealism — Marxism and the philosophic system of Dialectical Materialism. This has been done — perhaps very wrongly — partly for simple reasons of space, but chiefly because no independent worker who started from this point of view alone would ever approximate to the surrealist position, because he would almost inevitably remain within the official Communist limits, and would therefore bitterly oppose surrealism. The starting point must be psychoanalysis alone; this can develop into, and derive great assistance from. Dialectical Materialism. But with the present official Communist attitudes, the process is not reversible — unhappily.

What is the relation between the group who have worked with this theoretical basis, and scattered individuals who have used the same basis? How different are their conclusions? How similar is their work? These seem to me to be the real questions about surrealist sympathisers. Obviously they can only be settled — if they are ever settled — by discussion and negotiation. But as a preliminary to such discussion, it would be wise to define the orthodox psychoanalytic theories about art, as far as they go, so that it would be possible to see who departs from them, and how. The following notes are intended to indicate some of the main aspects of this orthodox doctrine.

Diver 5
III. a. The whole position is based on the acceptance of the hypothesis of causation, on the assumption that any observed phenomenon has a cause: that this cause is of a material kind (i.e. not an act of God in any sense): and that it is theoretically possible to ascertain this cause or causes, with varying degrees of probability.
      This hypothesis rules out at once all ideas of ‘inspiration,’ ‘aesthetic intuition,’ since they imply the notion of free-will: — the artist, by a special dispensation, creates something out of nothing, something which cannot be ‘explained away’ in terms of its causes.
      Like any other phenomenon, the work of art has causes, and these can be ascertained theoretically. It may happen, of course, that it is at the moment impossible, through defects in experimental technique etc., to ascertain these causes with any degree of certainty. But that is no reason at all for supposing that they cannot be ascertained at any time.
      b. The difficulties of discovering the causation of artistic activity have already been roughly indicated in the questions put into the mouth of the educated artist. It appears that art as an activity contributes nothing to the upkeep of the individual.; it rarely obtains for him a sufficiency of money for rent and food, and does nothing to gratify sexual requirements.
      Now it should be noticed that these difficulties are created by regarding man from a purely biological point of view, as an organism in an environment, with the usual implications of such a picture. And as long as this point of view is maintained, it is hard to see how the difficulties can be solved. A poor solution is suggested without much conviction by biologists and physiologists, who point to the existence of ‘play-activity’ in animals: — a kind of activity apparently without aim such as food or sexual satisfaction. Art might be the human equivalent of such play-activity, but there are obvious differences which make the parallel almost worthless: — for example, the play of animals involves muscular activity, perhaps in itself pleasurable, or serving as a motor discharge of internal stimulation (e.g. glandular), but most forms of artistic creation involve only a negligible amount of muscular movement.
      c. Psychoanalysis suggests solutions, in the first place by replacing the biological conception of man by a conception of man by a conception of its own — a new picture, in which the ‘organism’ of biology becomes only one part of the human individual, his conscious mind, while the environment is a double one, the outside world, and the inside world — the instinctual forces within the individual. The task of this organism* is not a simple one of direct war with the environment, as in the biological picture, but the much more complicated one of mediation between the two environments, whose demands always conflict in some way.

* This use of the word organism to describe only a part of the inside of an animal skin would only disturb those who have never tried to define exactly ‘organism.’

      This picture of the human situation is more useful than the biological one in any consideration of cultural factors, since culture is peculiar to man, and is obviously related with the characteristic which differentiates him from other animals — the great development of consciousness. Biology, in neglecting this characteristic — in having no technique for dealing with it — must necessarily fail to see the peculiar nature of the problems of man. Psychoanalysis may not be the only way of approaching these problems, but at the moment it is the clearest.
      The peculiar difficulty of satisfying human instincts appears to result from the fact that impossible conditions are attached to their satisfaction. For example, in the typical case, the infant is stimulated in a number of ways by its mother, and associates pleasure closely with her (e.g. in suckling, washing, and frank caresses). In the terms of Pavlov, the presence of the mother conditions the reflexes of pleasure. But it may happen that in later life, the individual fails to abolish this state of affairs, or to establish new conditions for his pleasures. He may continue to require the presence of the mother quite literally, and is then debarred from direct discharge of his feelings by those incest-taboos which seem to be so fundamental in human society. Or it may happen that at the infantile stage, some portion of the body other than the normal erotogenic zones is very much over-stimulated, and behaves as if it were erotogenic; obviously if this condition continues into adult life it can produce a serious situation, again by attaching impossible conditions to instinctual satisfaction.
      To some extent, even normal human beings suffer from these difficulties. Fortunately, however, there is a way out of the difficulty. The instinctual forces do not seem to care very much if the conditions for their fulfilment are provided in actuality, or in phantasy. That is to say, they will generally be satisfied if the situation to which they are accustomed is presented in the form of vivid memory-traces, worked up into a fairly coherent and life-like imitation of reality. Dreams provide the most universal example of this process. In them, instincts find fulfilment in phantasy-situations. In the waking life of primitive peoples, magic of all kinds does the same thing. And in the waking life of more civilised peoples, art, the lineal descendant of magic and religion, takes over the same function. Psychoanalysis has described a large number of parallels between dreams, primitive myths and rituals, and civilised art; it is unnecessary to repeat these in detail, but it must be understood that they form the basis of the theory of art based on psychoanalysis.
      d. There is one major difficulty in developing this theory more fully. I have begged the question by saying above ‘even normal human beings suffer from these difficulties.’ What are normal human beings? There seems to be good reason for believing that the general situation is common to all men — the difficulties face everyone. But it is also clear that some people surmount them much more successfully than others, and that some reactions to the situation are much better than others. Yet the criteria of success, and of the value of the reactions, are very obscure. For example, there are many striking similarities between art and hysteria. In hysteria, parts of the body are made to represent dramatically the situations of unconscious phantasies: — the intestine plays complicated games with its contents, instead of digesting and excreting them, the skin, instead of recording stimuli in the ordinary way for the guidance of the organism, develops anaesthesias and paraesthesias which interfere with its ordinary function, and serve the ends, apparently, not of utility, but of pleasure, and the muscles exhaust themselves in taking up positions which have no useful purpose. In fact the instinctual forces treat the body as a piece of plastic material, and shape it into forms which have a definite meaning. The plastic artist appears to do very much the same thing, except that he employs material from the external world instead of his own body. But is this an essential and important difference between the hysteric and the artist?
      Similarly the world created by a poet or a painter may approximate very closely to the worlds created by people confined in asylums. What is the difference between the two? Is there a real difference?

Nosferatu psychoanalysed
IV. I have said that these are only rough notes, and no complete conclusion is to be expected from them. On the whole, however, to return to the original subject — that of sympathy with surrealism — it seems probable that the surrealists and their sympathisers should be able to find a considerable body of common doctrine of a very useful and important kind in psychoanalytic theory of art. It will, however, consist mainly of parallels drawn between various expressions of the unconscious instinctual forces, and the problem of distinguishing between normal and abnormal, social and asocial expressions remains almost untouched, both by psychoanalytic theory and by surrealism. It is here that the difficulties and differences of opinion will occur: — and it is here, probably, that dialectical Materialism will perform its most useful work.



Check out this author’s work: Bookstores in Britain, and in the United States

Jacket 20 — December 2002
  Contents page
Select other issues of the magazine from the | Jacket catalog | read about Jacket |
Other links: | top | homepage | bookstores | literary links | internet design |
Copyright Notice: Please respect the fact that this material is copyright. It is made available here without charge for personal use only. It may not be stored, displayed, published, reproduced, or used for any other purpose
Cambridge Scenic Vignettes by John Tranter

This material is copyright © the Estate of Hugh Sykes Davies and Jacket magazine 2002
The URL address of this page is
http://jacketmagazine.com/20/hsd-symp.html